![]() |
19TH-CENTURY PHILOSOPHY: FROM KANT TO NIETZSCHE LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais
CHARTS:
LECTURE ONE: KANT'S RECEPTION OF ENLIGHTENMENT IDEALS: NOTES ON CHRISOPHER NOLAN'S MEMENTO: HOLDING WORDS AND IMAGES TOGETHER: READING NOTES ON GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: INTRODUCTION: READING NOTES ON GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: HUMAN SPONTANEITY AND THE NATURAL ORDER: READING NOTES ON GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: AUTONOMY AND THE MORAL ORDER: READING NOTES ON GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: AESTHETIC TASTE, TELEOLOGY, AND THE WORLD ORDER: READING NOTES ON GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: THE 1790s: FICHTE: KANT'S THREE BASIC QUESTIONS AND THEIR CORRESPONDING "CRITIQUES": KANT AS AN ADVOCATE OF ENLIGHTENMENT IDEALS: HUME AWAKENS KANT FROM HIS DOGMATIC SLUMBERS: THE" COPERNICAN REVOLUTION" IN PHILOSOPHY: THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL RESTRICTION: THE SPLIT OR ‘DIREMPTED” SELF: KANT’S REVOLUTIONARY ORIENTATION TO SELF KNOWLEDGE: KANT ASKS THREE BASIC QUESTIONS: Kant’s philosophy – which he calls “transcendental idealism” – is exceedingly complex. His famous Critiques – The Critique of Pure Reason, The Critique of Practical Reason, and The Critique of Judgment (NB: along with subsequent writings) – address three different questions: What can I know?, What ought I to do?, and What can I hope for? In order to understand how Kant answers these questions, it is important to place him within the critical juncture of Western history known as “The Enlightenment.” KANT AS AN ADVOCATE OF ENLIGHTENMENT IDEALS: Kant inherits and affirms the Enlightenment promise of human maturation into “The Age of Reason.” Humans find themselves caught within a “self-incurred immaturity” (selbsts-verschuldeten Unmuendigkeit). Kant understands this immaturity – literally, the inability to speak for oneself (Unmuendigkeit) – in terms of the failure or refusal to rely upon one’s own reason. In such a state of such immaturity, one simply takes over, on the received authority of others, answers to questions fundamental to the conduct of life: e.g. What is knowledge, What ought I to do, What may I hope for.” Some have argued that Kant’s claim of a “self-incurred immaturity” is paradoxical: how could immaturity be “self incurred” or “due to oneself.” Kant’s position is, however, consistent and clear. To take traditional doctrine as true is itself an act of certifying or endorsing its claim to being an authoritative answer. Given this feature of taking as true, it’s incumbent upon a human being to explain why he or she has taken something as true or right. For Kant, given that we are in the business of asking questions and accepting answers – and, hence, response-able for what we take as authoritative – the elemental question whether we neglect or assume our vocation as reason-able. Cowardice and laziness account for why someone is “immature”: both are ways of accepting some charge or task as incumbent upon one while nevertheless neglecting to carry through with the responsibility. DOGMATISM (Rationalism), SKEPTICISM (Hume's Empiricism), AND CRITICISM (Kant’s Transcendental Idealism): Kant distinguishes between three phases of philosophy: dogmatism, skepticism, and criticism.
As an empiricist, Hume works within the
"theory of ideas" paradigm of philosophy. At the same time,
however, he shows how it necessarily leads to skepticism. Hume assumes
the theory of ideas, but he is the only philosopher in this tradition
who works out with rigor and consistency its necessary conclusions.
If we assume the theory of ideas, Hume argues, we must accept that knowledge
is not a product of reason but, instead, an animal propensity or habit.
Reduced to its bare essentials, Hume argues the flow of ideas in the
mind can never provide a basis for saying anything about what lies “beyond”
them, “out there,” so to speak, in the “real world.”
Moreover, the flow of ideas is not up to us but a matter of animal compulsion:
they just happen, whether we will them or not. If what we can experience
is our own ideas, then we can never stand outside our ideas, putting
them to one side, and appraise how such ideas might correspond to independently
existing reality, put to the other side. Hume is the first philosopher
to consistently work out the necessary conclusion of the theory of ideas
as skepticism. In short, Hume works out the reduction ad absurdum of
the theory of ideas. Two skeptical conclusions emerge from the second paradigm of philosophy: one about what we can know and the other about what we ought to do. Hume’s “theoretical” philosophy – his “epistemology” or “theory of knowledge” – is that what we call “rational knowledge” is really animal faith. We can have no knowledge of what lies beyond our consciousness, so we don’t have knowledge of reality. Hume’s “practical” philosophy – his “moral theory” or “ethics” – is that “morality” is really a matter of animal passions and sympathies and, most importantly, that “reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions.” In other words, for Hume our use of reason can give us neither insight into what we ought to do nor motivation to do what reason might dictate. Reason can only calculate how we might more efficiently pursue our desires, but it cannot tell what we ought to desire. Reason is at best a tool for calculating how we can most efficiently realize our desires; it is not capable of demonstrating what ends we ought to pursue. In several contexts – letters
to Helmholz and in Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysic – Kant
confesses that it was Hume who awoke him from his “dogmatic slumber.”
Hume epistemological and moral skepticism represented for Kant the abject
failure of philosophy to be raise itself into a “science”
– that is, a serious inquiry. Kant’s “critical”
philosophy responds to this historical junction of the exhaustion or
incredibility of the two historical paradigms of Western philosophy:
namely, ancient metaphysics and modern philosophy of mind.
Kant model of experience arises from a unique conception of the discovery of geometry or geometrical demonstrations, presumably by Thales, as Kant reads the account of Diogenes Laertius. Demonstrations in Geometry – say the Pythagorean Theorem – are neither a matter of extending our sensory awareness of triangles – looking more carefully -- nor unpacking or concepts – defining “triangle” or “planes.” Instead, it’s a matter of actively constructing, dynamically diagramming, or imaginatively framing the object. The triangle is not given in perception or defined in thought but, instead, constructed by an active subject setting something before itself in demonstration. In short, Kant takes Thales’s discovery of geometry as the discovery of an active, form-giving subject that actively frames, constructs, or organizes the object of experience. This pre-figuration is not a distortion of something pre-given. On the contrary, this active forming makes experience possible in the first place. The essential point for Kant is that the “I” actively places or presents objects to itself, and without this activity there would be no subject relating to an object. Today, we take this insight for granted in the idea humans are actively “processing information” to make a relation to something possible. The “Copernican Revolution” in philosophy begins, then, with this elemental insight: the “I” of experience is an active, form-legislating subject. The “I” is not a passive “mirror” that passively reflects what is given before it but, instead, an active “lamp” that illuminates its surroundings to bring things to appearance. The metaphor is, of course, very limited. The key point, however, is wide ranging: the “I” actively presents or poses objects to itself. Commonly understood, “dogmatism”
characterizes a type of thinking that isn’t “philosophical”
at all because still dependent upon mythological and religious assumptions.
As Kant more narrowly defines it, dogmatism is the “rationalist”
method of philosophical inquiry that claims knowledge of things by examination
of their concepts alone – that is “the presumption that
it is possible to make progress with pure knowledge, according to principles,
from concepts alone” (BXXXV) [underlining my own: C.L.]. Kant
himself, in his “pre-critical phase,” was a rationalist
philosopher, and he is now aware that such thinking naively rests upon
unexamined assumptions that should be critically examined: “Dogmatism
is thus the dogmatic procedure of pure reason, without previous criticism
of its own powers” (BXXXV). In the precise terms Kant sets out,
he simply raises the question of whether there is synthetic knowledge
known a priori and how it is at all possible: “Now the proper
problem of pure reason is contained in the question: How are a priori
synthetic judgments possible” (B19). Hume emerges as the arch
skeptic who, Kant claims, woke him from his (Kant’s) “dogmatic
slumber.” In the early 18th century, Hume carries out a devastating
skeptical attack upon the possibility of a priori synthetic knowledge.
Knowledge, for Hume, is based upon experience – that is, justified
a posteriori (i.e. “on the basis of experience). “Among
philosophers,” Kant writes, “David Hume came nearest to
envisaging this problem, but still was very far from conceiving it with
sufficient definiteness and universality. He occupied himself exclusively
with the synthetic proposition regarding the connection of an effect
with its cause (principium causalities), and he believed himself to
have shown that such an a priori proposition is entirely impossible.
If we accept his conclusions, then all that we call metaphysics is mere
delusion whereby we fancy ourselves to have rational insight into what,
in actual fact, is borrowed solely from experience, and under the influence
of custom has taken the illusory semblance of necessity.” (B19-20). THE "COPERNICAN REVOLUTION" IN PHILOSOPHY: Kant’s answer to Hume’s question – what is the origin and justification of our knowledge – is as shocking in its simplicity as it is revolutionary in its novelty: objects conform to our way of knowing.
THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL RESTRICTION: Given Kant’s claim that experience is made possible by our form-legislating activity, it’s crucial that we “restrict” our claims to knowledge. We do indeed have knowledge of objects, but we can’t move from the premise that we experience objects as, for instance, (universally and necessarily) causally determined that, therefore, objects in themselves are such. We can certainly think that different types of beings might have radically different forms of experience, and this means that we can consider the object in abstraction from how it can be given to us. This is all Kant means by “thing in itself”: it’s the same thing that we experience, considered or thought about in abstraction from the modes of our experience. Do not think that the “thing experience” and “thing in itself” are two different types of things. Instead, think of it as the distinction between two ways of considering one and the same object: namely, as conforming to our experiential abilities, on the one hand, and as something that may be differently experienced. Kant famously claims that he has found it necessary to restrict knowledge to make room for faith. What he means by this is that he restricts knowledge to our perceptual and conceptual abilities to make room for our being able to consider something “in itself” – that is, in abstraction from its being an object of knowledge. The most important result of Kant’s theory of knowledge is that we can consider a human being from two different perspectives: as an “appearance” – that is, as a natural object subject to the laws of nature – and as “thing in itself” – that is, as the same person but now thought of as being a free agent in a social world not subject to the laws of nature. Kant’s central intention here is to establish that it is legitimate to consider a human being from two such different perspectives: as a natural things (physiological determinism) and social agent (free to act on the basis of moral principles. By distinguishing two ways of taking one and the same thing, Kant combines the natural sciences and their objectifying approach to human life, on the one hand, with our conception of ourselves as agents with freedom and responsibility.
KANT’S
MORAL THEORY
The contrast Kant presents with this formulation is the basic distinction between “things” and conscious “agents.” A being with a will is not a mechanism or physical system whose various states are simply the causal effect of prior states. The concept of a rational, natural being is one that contains the idea of a being who acts “in accordance to the conception of law” -- i.e. on the basis of thought or insight into a law. The basic idea here is that the actions of a rational agent are not simply the effect of its strongest drives, urges, desires, needs, or conditionings. Henry Allison calls this model of agency the “battle ground” model, because the “strongest” desire determines the outcome or action of the will. According to the “battle ground model of agency,” attributed to David Hume, the will consists of a number of competing desires of varying degrees of strength that drive the agent in various possible practical directions -- toward the satisfaction of those drives. This is the model of agency that Freud envisions in his early works, of a biological being whose existence is determined by its various drives. The strongest desire drives the organism toward what will satisfy it -- say, food or sex. Against this conception of a single plane or arena of erotic drive conflict, Kant here introduces a quite different, “juridical” model of agency. Kant’s basic idea is that a rational will consists of two tiers or levels, the first indeed consists of a multiplicity of possibly competing desires, but the second stands like a judge to whom such desires offer petition, who must, in response, offer a hearing and judgment, acting only under a ruling or “conception” of what such a course of action would consist in. Allison calls this the “Incorporation thesis,” because desires (first level) must be taken up or incorporated by a judge (the agent) under a rule — a ruling, articulation, or clarification of what such a course of action would be — and it is the conception of such rules that determines the will, not the desires as such. Allison presents the incorporation thesis as defining Kant’s model of rational agency:
Kant’s model of agency reflects the basic tenor of his Copernican turn to an active, form-legislating subject:
Kant contrasts the concept of an infinite or divine will — one determined by reason alone, absolutely free from any sensuous determination whatsoever — from the concept of a finite will — one that is both rational and sensible. As finite, the human will is both sensible and rational. As natural beings, we are equipped with sensibility, by means of which we are able to intuit both natural objects and our own biological condition — that is, our needs, desires and emotions. As rational beings, on the other hand, we are equipped with reason, by means of which we are able to raise the question of what end we ought to pursue. This dual rational-empirical nature defines our finitude; unlike a purely rational will, whose thought alone determines action. In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant demonstrates how this model of rational agency -- articulated in the Incorporation Thesis -- is presupposed in our ordinary understanding of morality. He will then raise another fundamental claim regarding human action: namely, that freedom and morality reciprocally imply one another. First, however, Kant ties the notion of the goodness of an action to the will that acts from a rule or “maxim” of duty. The goodness of the will is not derived from the goodness of its results. Three propositions about the relation between a good will and duty follow:
Notice several things about this passage.
First, the feeling is “self-produced” by our imposing
the law on ourselves. Second, as self-produced, reverence is distinct
from inclination or fear, although analogous to the former in being
“self-imposed” and to the latter in being “necessary
in itself.” The “immediate determination of the will by
the law and consciousness of this determination” -- in short,
our sense as agents of being able to act for the sake of duty or solely
to do the right thing -- “demolishes my self-love,” according
to Kant. The idea here is that “reverence” is the intuition
we have of ourselves, of our being able to act “according to
the conception of law.” But what type of law is this?
This is Kant’s most famous contribution to moral theory, his formulation of the “categorical imperative.” To act on the basis of “self-love” or self interest would be to take as a general rule or maxim some course of action that satisfies a desire that I happen to have as a particular agent. When I want X, then I will do Y. The problem with such a maxim or rule is that, while it affirms my own particularity, it can not be rule for all rational agents, who may well differ in regard to their own desires It does not, then, affirm what I have in common with other human beings, namely freedom. The core of Kant’s moral theory is a claim that is now called the “Reciprocity Thesis”: “freedom and unconditional practical law reciprocally imply each other” (Kpr V 5:28;29). The basic claim is that I am free if, and only if, I am bound by the moral law. This is the central claim of a “deontological” moral theory, and the central concept of this moral theory is the notion of autonomy (“Auto” = “self” and “Nomos” = “law”; hence, a being capable of binding itself to its own legislation). The essential idea is that I am a law unto myself -- in other words, that I impose laws upon myself -- if and only if the moral law -- the categorical imperative -- is binding. The best way to appreciate this is to see that the bindingness or validity of the moral law is the only way I can ever become cognizant of my freedom, understood as autonomy or the ability to impose law upon myself. Only if I can “universalize” my maxim — that is, act on a maxim that I can at the same time will to be a maxim for all rational agents — can I realize my autonomy, my freedom from the desires that I just happen to have as a particular being. In short, I am first cognizant that I am free from the particular desires, drives or tendencies I happen to have as an empirical being when I bind myself to the moral law, which requires me to ask whether all rational beings could will some maxim. If I act “autonomously,” then I act on a rational basis, on the basis of a self-imposed law, on the universal condition of rational agents and not on the basis of my own contingent particularity. If I act on the basis of some “material” condition of my particular existence — that is, on the basis of some desire that nature or social conditioning has given me — then I act “heteronomously,” since the “law” or rule of action originates, in effect, “from outside,” as an accident of nature, not from “inside” me, my essential condition as a choosing or “spontaneous” agent. The upshot is simply this: Kant’s notion of freedom is freedom from our natural condition as what determines our actions. THE SPLIT OR ‘DIREMPTED” SELF: KANT’S REVOLUTIONARY ORIENTATION TO SELF KNOWLEDGE:Kant’s analysis of experience or knowledge begins by raising the question of how experience is possible in the first place. As we have seen, the key to understanding Kant’s “model of mind” is the discovery that the self is active, form-legislating, synthesizing self or “I.” Kant first distinguishes intuitions – the immediate “representations” or, better, presentations – from concepts – the mediate “representation” or, better, grasping or taking of intuitions as something. As Pinkard notes,
As we have seen, the transcendental deduction leads to “epistemological restriction”: that is, the necessity of limiting our knowledge to that which conforms to our intuitive and conceptual forms. We do have experience of things, but we must distinguish between two ways of considering such objects of experience. First, they are appearances of objects or, said equivalently, phenomena (things that “show” themselves), but we must also recognize that another being – a god for instance – might not have such forms. We have to consider one and the same thing, then, from two different perspectives: i.e. as phenomena (Things-in-appearance) and noumena (Things-in-themselves). Kant’s conception of the self is subject to the same epistemological restriction. If we experience the self as an natural object, then we do so as something that appears in time and space, as causally situated within a surrounding nature, as an causally determined “internally” as animal with needs, desires, motility, sensibility, physical abilities and limitations, etc., etc. Moreover, as social animals, we are raised up in social settings that have a palpable effect upon what we see, say, do, and feel, and the cultural circumstances in which we live also have effects upon our person that are studied as Anthropology, widely understood as the empirical study of what shapes human beings. These empirical studies, however, must be limited to the human self insofar as it appears as a natural object. The human “I” is also, however, the subject or “seat” of experience, and it is this “logical” subject that cannot be understood as a natural thing. Kant is forced by his epistemological restriction to distinguish, then, two different senses of the self. As Kant notes, “That I am conscious of myself is a thought that already contains a two-fold I” (WP, pp. 73 & 270). The transcendental I is, Kant writes, a “mere prefix [designating] a thing of indeterminate signification” (MF, p. 543, p. 103). As a “completely empty representation ‘I’,” Kant writes, “we cannot even say that this is a concept, but only that it is a bare consciousness which accompanies all concepts” (CPR, A 436/B 404). As Caygil notes, “It is but the logical terminus of a process of abstracting from the predicates of knowledge to a postulated, ultimate subject which underlies them and which cannot be further specified.” (Caygil, p. 234). In one of the most famous passages of CPR, Kant states, “this I, he or it (the thing) which thinks, nothing further is represented than a transcendental subject of the thoughts = X” (CPR, A 346/B 404). Now, the epistemological restriction
prohibits the illicit conflation of the logical I of thought and action
with any substance or thing in the world. If one treats the transcendental
subject as the object of knowledge – that is, as phenomena or
substantial thing – then we would commit what Kant calls a “paralogism”:
that is, a (transcendental) logical fallacy of conflating something
that is subject to the forms of intuition (space and time) and the
categories of the understanding, on the one hand, with something that
is necessarily distinct from any such thing: namely, the “empty”
logical subject of experience and action.
|